No. 95-8079 --UNITED STATES v. MEYERS
Circuit Judge, BRORBY, respectfully dissenting.
Because I do not believe it is the proper role of the
court to establish a factor-driven test to be used to define
what a religion is, I respectfully dissent from my colleagues.
The ability to define religion is the power to deny freedom of
religion. The ethereal and personal nature of religion has
posed problems for most courts that have attempted to define
it. See Wiggins v. Sargent, 753 F.2d 663, 666 (8th Cir. 1985)
("The determination of whether a belief is religious or not is
an extremely delicate task which must be approached with
caution."); Africa v. Pennsylvania, 662 F.2d 1025, 1031 (3rd
Cir. 1981) ("judges are ill-equipped to examine the breadth
and content of an avowed religion"), cert. denied, 456 U.S.
908 (1982); United States v. Kauten, 133 F.2d 703, 708 (2d
Cir. 1943) (recognizing that the definition of religion "is
found in the history of the human race and is incapable of
compression into a few words"); see also Brown v. Dade
Christian Schools, Inc., 556 F.2d 310 (5th Cir. 1977) (judges
filed two concurrences and two dissenting opinions in a case
attempting to define religion in order to determine whether a
religious school's policy of racial discrimination was
religious or social or political in nature), cert. denied, 434
U.S. 1063 (1978).
In Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205, 215-16 (1972), the
Supreme Court held that religious beliefs are distinct from
philosophical and personal choices but failed to provide a
test or a definition against which lower courts could hold the
religious claims of petitioners to determine whether the
claims warrant constitutional protection. Many courts have
felt compelled by the distinction made in Yoder to establish
a definition of religion. See United States v. Ward, 989 F.2d
1015, 1017 (9th Cir. 1992); Quaring v. Peterson, 728 F.2d
1121, 1123 (8th Cir. 1984), aff'd, 472 U.S. 478 (1985);
Africa, 662 F.2d at 1031. We, however, had declined to do so
until now. In Werner v. McCotter, 49 F.3d 1476, 1479 n.1
(10th Cir.), cert. denied, 115 S. Ct. 2625 (1995), we
recognized the distinction in Yoder and then found "a
plaintiff, however, need not hew to any particular religious
orthodoxy; it is enough for the plaintiff to demonstrate that
a government has interfered with the exercise or expression of
her or his own deeply held faith." Id. at 1480. I believe an
approach that prevents the courts from evaluating the
orthodoxy and expression of the individual is the approach
most in keeping with the mandates of the Constitution and the
Supreme Court. For, it seems to me that the free exercise of
religion which we are all guaranteed by the First Amendment
necessarily includes the rights of individuals to define their
own religion. Accordingly, it is an unproductive and
unnecessarily invasive exercise for the courts to attempt to
evaluate an individual's religious claims and practices
against any set standard of preconceived notions of what types
of religious beliefs are valid of being recognized by the
courts. In fact, in the conscientious objector context, the
Supreme Court has held
"Men may believe what they cannot prove. They may not be put to the proof of their religious doctrines or beliefs. Religious experiences which are as real as life to some may be incomprehensible to others."
Local boards and courts in this sense are not free to reject
beliefs because they consider them "incomprehensible."
United States v. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163, 184-85 (1965) (quoting
United States v. Ballard, 322 U.S. 78, 86 (1944)). By
attempting to evaluate another's religion with a factor-driven
test we have essentially gutted the Free Exercise Clause of
its meaning and are ignoring the Supreme Court's cautionary
words that a person's views can be "incomprehensible" to the
court and still be religious in his or her "own scheme of
things." Id.
In an early opinion addressing the Constitutional meaning of
"religion," the Supreme Court first recognized that the word
religion is not defined in the Constitution and then turned to
Thomas Jefferson's views that "religion is a matter which lies
solely between man and his God; that he owes account to none
other for his faith or his worship; that the legislative
powers of the government reach actions only, and not opinions,
— I contemplate with sovereign reverence that act of the
whole American people which declared that their legislature
should 'make no law respecting an establishment of religion or
prohibiting the free exercise thereof,' thus building a wall
of separation between church and State. Adhering to this
expression of the supreme will of the nation in behalf of the
rights of conscience, I shall see with sincere satisfaction
the progress of those sentiments which tend to restore man to
all his natural rights, convinced he
has no natural right in opposition to his social duties."
Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145, 164 (1878). The Court then held that Jefferson's
words "may be accepted almost as an authoritative declaration of the scope and effect of
the amendment thus secured. Congress was deprived of all legislative power over mere
opinion, but was left free to reach actions which were in violation of social duties or
subversive of good order." Id.; see also, Ballard, 322 U.S. at 87 (noting the intent of the
"fathers of the Constitution" to provide for the "the widest possible toleration of
conflicting views" and protection of religious beliefs, even those deemed incredible or
preposterous by most people); Davis v. Beason, 133 U.S. 333, 342 (1890) ("with man's
relations to his Maker and the obligations he may think they impose, and the manner in
which an expression shall be made by him of his belief on those subjects, no interference
can be permitted"). The Court expressed the same sentiment in Cantwell v. Connecticut,
310 U.S. 296, 303-04 (1940), when it held
The constitutional inhibition of legislation on the subject of religion has a
double aspect. On the one hand, it forestalls compulsion by law of the
acceptance of any creed or the practice of any form of worship. Freedom of
conscience and freedom to adhere to such religious organization or form of
worship as the individual may choose cannot be restricted by law. On the
other hand, it safeguards the free exercise of the chosen form of religion.
Thus the Amendment embraces two concepts, — freedom to believe and
freedom to act. The first is absolute but, in the nature of things, the second
cannot be.
The absoluteness of the freedom to believe and the freedom to exercise a chosen form of
religion is significantly diluted by a court sponsored inquiry into what the individual
believes and how he or she expresses those beliefs. Although the factors provided by the
majority opinion arguably are content neutral, they still require an individual to provide
evidence concerning what he or she believes and how he or she expresses those beliefs so
that the courts may then judge whether the beliefs and practices are acceptable enough to
be labeled a "religion" under our definition. Such scrutiny clearly usurps the individual's
right to believe and to express those beliefs however he or she chooses.
The Supreme Court has also cautioned that a determination of what is a religious
belief or practice is "not to turn upon a judicial perception of the particular belief or
practice in question; religious beliefs need not be acceptable, logical, consistent or
comprehensible to others in order to merit First Amendment protection." Thomas v.
Review Bd. of Indiana Employment Sec. Div., 450 U.S. 707, 714 (1981). Furthermore,
"it is no business of courts to say that what is a religious practice or activity for one group
is not religion under the protection of the First Amendment." Fowler v. Rhode Island,
345 U.S. 67, 70 (1953); see also Hernandez v. Commissioner, 490 U.S. 680, 693 (1989)
("under the First Amendment, the IRS can reject otherwise valid claims of religious
benefit only on the ground that a taxpayers' alleged beliefs are not sincerely held, but not
on the grounds that such beliefs are inherently irreligious"). By applying a broad factor-
driven test as advocated by the majority opinion, the subjective perceptions of the court
are necessarily invoked in evaluating whether what the individual claims to be religious is
indeed religious. It also requires the court to judge the practices of the individual to see if
they are indeed "religious." This test clearly violates the spirit, if not the intent, of the
First Amendment.
The Second Circuit relied on the works of American philosopher William James to
define religion as:
"the feelings, acts, and experiences of individual men in their solitude, so
far as they apprehend themselves to stand in relation to whatever they may
consider the divine." W. James, The Varieties of Religious Experience 31
(1910). In referring to an individual's relation to what he considers the
divine, Professor James used the word 'divine' in its broadest sense as
denoting any object that is godlike, whether it is or is not a specific deity.
Id. at 34. Therefore, under the Religion Clauses, everyone is entitled to
entertain such view respecting his relations to what he considers the divine
and the duties such relationship imposes as may be approved by that
person's conscience, and to worship in any way such person thinks fit so
long as this is not injurious to the equal rights of others.
United States v. Moon, 718 F.2d 1210, 1227 (2d Cir. 1983), cert. denied, 466 U.S. 971
(1984). I believe this definition comes the closest to capturing the inherently elusive,
spiritual and personal nature of religion. I also believe that under such a definition it is
inappropriate, if not impossible, to evaluate or analyze the religious beliefs of an
individual under a factor-driven approach. The appropriateness of the above definition
lies in its openness, which also makes it unworkable as a standard for those seeking
concrete guidance in this area.
It seems to me the better practice is not to engage in any type of an attempt to
define religion and instead to assume, without deciding, the validity of an individual's
sincerely held religious beliefs for purposes of constitutional protection. See Smith v.
Board of Sch. Comm'rs of Mobile County, 827 F.2d 684, 689 (11th Cir. 1987) (assuming
secular humanism is a religion for purposes of the Establishment Clause); United States v.
Middleton, 690 F.2d 820, 824 (11th Cir. 1982) (assuming Ethiopian Zion Coptic Church
is a valid religion), cert. denied, 460 U.S. 1051 (1983); see also Jones v. Bradley, 590
F.2d 294, 296-97 (9th Cir. 1979) (assuming members of the Universal Life Church are
entitled to First Amendment protection). Under this approach if an individual makes a
claim that a government law substantially burdens his or her sincere religious beliefs I
would assume the validity of the religion without analyzing the tenets or practices of the
religion to see if they fit some preconceived vision of what a religion is. This approach
may seem radical; however, it is the only way we can assure an individual the absolute
freedom to worship what he or she chooses in the way in which he or she chooses. It is
important to note that such a practice would not send us down a "slippery slope" or create
a mass shield which any criminal could use to thwart prosecution for crimes done in the
name of religion. It has never been the law in this country that religious beliefs prevent
the government from regulating criminal or other harmful actions of individuals.
Cantwell, 310 U.S. at 303. Under the Religious Freedom and Restoration Act, after
raising the defense of religion, the individual must show that his or her religious beliefs
are sincerely held and were substantially burdened. If this showing is made, then the
government may still prevail if it shows that such burden is necessary to further a
compelling government interest and that the law is the least restrictive means of
furthering that interest. 42 U.S.C. 2000bb-1. This law enforces the absolute freedom of
the individual to believe and worship whatever he or she chooses, but clearly prevents
him or her from freely acting on these beliefs in ways that are harmful to others.
In this case, I would assume the validity of Mr. Meyers' religious beliefs and
affirm the district court's findings that these beliefs are sincerely held and substantially
burdened by the laws in question. Although I am confident that the government will have
no problem meeting its burden of proof, Olsen v. DEA, 878 F.2d 1458, 1462-63 (D.C.
Cir. 1989) (government has a compelling interest in regulating the use of marijuana and is
not required to accommodate sacremental use), cert. denied, 495 U.S. 906 (1990), it has
not yet been given an opportunity to do so. Therefore, in accordance with the
requirements of 42 U.S.C. 2000bb-1, I would reverse the district court's findings that
Mr. Meyers' sincerely held beliefs are not religious and I would remand to allow the
government an opportunity to meet its burden of showing that the laws involved serve a
compelling government interest and are the least restrictive means of meeting that
interest. See United States v. Bauer, 84 F.3d 1549, 1559 (9th Cir. 1996).